www.nmgpsy.com内蒙古心理网
The system as a bio-social mechanism of homeostatic regulation
Attachment theory, developed by John Bowlby (Bowlby, 1969; Bowlby, 1973; Bowlby, 1980), postulates a universal human need to form close affectional bonds. At its core is the reciprocity of early relationships, which is a precondition of normal development probably in all mammals, including humans (Hofer, 1995). The attachment behaviours of the human infant (e.g. proximity seeking, smiling, clinging) are reciprocated by adult attachment behaviours (touching, holding, soothing) and these responses strengthen the attachment behaviour of the infant toward that particular adult. The activation of attachment behaviours depends on the infant’s evaluation of a range of environmental signals which results in the subjective experience of security or insecurity. The experience of security is the goal of the attachment system, which is thus first and foremost a regulator of emotional experience (Sroufe, 1996). In this sense it lies at the heart of many forms of mental disorder and the entire psychotherapeutic enterprise.
None of us is born with the capacity to regulate our own emotional reactions. A dyadic regulatory system evolves where the infants’ signals of moment to moment changes in their state that are understood and responded to by the caregiver thereby achieving their regulation. The infant learns that arousal in the presence of the caregiver will not lead to disorganisation beyond his coping capabilities. The caregiver will be there to re-establish equilibrium. In states of uncontrollable arousal, the infant will come to seek physical proximity to the caregiver in the hope of soothing and the recovery of homeostasis. The infant’s behaviour by the end of the first year is purposeful, and apparently based on specific expectations. His past experiences with the caregiver are aggregated into representational systems which Bowlby (1973) termed ‘internal working models’. Thus, the attachment system is an open bio-social homeostatic regulatory system.
Patterns of attachment in infancy
The second great pioneer of attachment theory, Mary Ainsworth (1969; 1985; Ainsworth, Blehar, Waters, & Wall, 1978), developed the well-known laboratory based procedure for observing infant’s internal working models in action. Infants, briefly separated from their caregiver in a situation unfamiliar to them, show one of four patterns of behaviour. Infants classified as Secure explore readily in the presence of the primary caregiver, are anxious in the presence of the stranger and avoid her, are distressed by their caregivers’ brief absence, rapidly seek contact with the caregiver afterwards, and are reassured by this. The infant returns to exploration. Some infants, who appear to be made less anxious by separation, may not seek proximity with the caregiver following separation, and may not prefer the caregiver over the stranger; these infants are designated ‘Anxious/Avoidant’. A third category, ‘Anxious/Resistant’ infants show limited exploration and play, tend to be highly distressed by the separation, but have great difficulty in settling afterwards, showing struggling, stiffness, continued crying, or fuss in a passive way. The caregiver’s presence or attempts at comforting fail to reassure, and the infant’s anxiety and anger appear to prevent them from deriving comfort from proximity.
Secure infants’ behaviour is based on the experience of well co-ordinated, sensitive interactions where the caregiver is rarely over-arousing and is able to restabilise the child’s disorganising emotional responses. Therefore, they remain relatively organised in stressful situations. Negative emotions feel less threatening, and can be experienced as meaningful and communicative (Grossman, Grossmann, & Schwan, 1986; Sroufe, 1979; Sroufe, 1996).
Anxious/Avoidantly attached children are presumed to have had experiences where their emotional arousal was not restabilised by the caregiver, or where they were over aroused through intrusive parenting; therefore they over-regulatetheir affect and avoid situations that are likely to be distressing. Anxious/Resistantly attached children under-regulate, heightening their expression of distress possibly in an effort to elicit the expectable response of the caregiver. There is a low threshold for threat, and the child becomes preoccupied with having contact with the caregiver, but frustrated even when it is available (Sroufe, 1996).
A fourth group of infants exhibits seemingly undirected behaviour, giving the impression of disorganisation and disorientation (Main & Solomon, 1990). Infants who manifest freezing, hand clapping, head-banging, the wish to escape the situation even in the presence of the caregiver, are referred to as ‘Disorganised/Disoriented’. It is generally held that for such infants the caregiver has served as a source of both fear and reassurance, thus arousal of the attachment behavioural system produces strong conflicting motivations. Not surprisingly, a history of severe neglect or physical or sexual abuse is often associated with this pattern (Cicchetti & Beeghly, 1987; Main & Hesse, 1990). I would like to consider this group in much greater detail, this afternoon.
The continuity of patterns of attachment
Bowlby proposed that internal working models of the self and others provide prototypes for all later relationships. Such models are relatively stable across the lifespan (Collins & Read, 1994). Early experiences of flexible access to feelings are regarded as formative by attachment theorists. The autonomous sense of self emerges fully from secure parent-infant relationships (Emde & Buchsbaum, 1990; Fonagy et al., 1995a; Lieberman & Pawl, 1990). Most importantly the increased control of the secure child permits him to move toward the ownership of inner experience, and toward understanding self and others as intentional beings whose behaviour is organised by mental states, thoughts, feelings, beliefs and desires (Fonagy et al., 1995a; Sroufe, 1990). Consistent with this, prospective longitudinal research has demonstrated that children with a history of secure attachment are independently rated as more resilient, self-reliant, socially oriented (Sroufe, 1983; Waters, Wippman, & Sroufe, 1979), empathic to distress (Kestenbaum, Farber, & Sroufe, 1989), with deeper relationships (Sroufe, 1983; Sroufe, Egeland, & Kreutzer, 1990).
Prediction from adult attachment measures
The stability of attachment is demonstrated by longitudinal studies of infants assessed with the Strange Situation and followed up in adolescence or young adulthood with the Adult Attachment Interview (AAI) (George, Kaplan, & Main, 1996). I assume most of you are familiar with this wonderful structured clinical instrument which elicits narrative histories of childhood attachment relationships – the characteristics of early relationships, experiences of separation, illness, punishment, loss, maltreatment or abuse. The AAI scoring system (Main & Goldwyn, 1994) classifies individuals intoSecure/Autonomous, Insecure/Dismissing, Insecure/Preoccupied or Unresolved with respect to loss or trauma, categories based on the structural qualities of narratives of early experiences. While autonomous individuals value attachment relationships, coherently integrate memories into a meaningful narrative and regard these as formative, insecure individuals are poor at integrating memories of experience with the meaning of that experience. Those dismissing of attachment show avoidance in denying memories, idealizing or devaluing (or both idealizing and devaluing) early relationships. Preoccupied individuals tend to be confused, angry or passive in relation to attachment figures, often still complaining of childhood slights, echoing the protests of the resistant infant. Unresolved individuals give indications of significant disorganisation in their attachment relationship representation in semantic or syntactic confusions in their narratives concerning childhood trauma or a recent loss. Again, we shall revisit this clinically most important group this afternoon.
Three major longitudinal studies (Hamilton, 1994; Main, 1997; Waters, Merrick, Albersheim, Treboux, & Crowell, 1995) have shown a 68-75% correspondence between attachment classifications in infancy and classifications in adulthood. This is an unparalleled level of consistency between behaviour observed in infancy and outcomes in adulthood. Obviously, such individual differences may well be maintained by consistent environments as well as by patterns laid down in the first year of life.
Attachment relationships play a key role in the transgenerational transmission of deprivation. Secure adults are 3 or 4 times more likely to have children who are securely attached to them (van IJzendoorn, 1995). This is true even where parental attachment is assessed before the birth of the child (Benoit & Parker, 1994; Fonagy, Steele, & Steele, 1991b; Radojevic, 1992; Steele, Steele, & Fonagy, 1996; Ward & Carlson, 1995). Parental attachment patterns predict variance in addition to temperament measures or contextual factors, such as life events, social support and psychopathology (Steele, Steele, & Fonagy, in preparation). How is such transgenerational transmission mediated? Genetics may appear to provide an obvious explanation. The early findings of an ongoing twin study in our laboratory have yielded no evidence of differential levels of concordance of attachment classification between identical and non-identical twins (Fearon, 1998). Attachment theorists have assumed that securely attached adults are more sensitive to their children’s needs thus fostering an expectation in the infant that dysregulation will be rapidly and effectively met (Belsky, Rosenberger, & Crnic, 1995; De Wolff & van IJzendoorn, 1997). Disappointingly, standard measures of caregiver sensitivity do not appear to explain at all well transgenerational consistencies in attachment classification (van IJzendoorn, 1995).
Attachment and mentalising: The move from a teleological to a mentalistic construal of attachment relationships in development
To do so, we have to explore a further aspect of the determinants of attachment. Mary Main and Inge Bretherton independently drew attention to what the philosopher Dennett called the "intentional stance". Dennett (1987) stressed that human beings try to understand each other in terms of mental states: thoughts and feelings, beliefs and desires, in order to make sense of and, even more important, to anticipate each others’ actions. If the child is able to attribute an unresponsive mother’s apparently rejecting behaviour to her sadness about a loss, rather than simply feeling helpless in the face of it, the child is protected from confusion and a negative view of himself. The hallmark of the intentional stance is the child’s recognition at around 3-4 years that behaviour may be based on a mistaken belief. Developmentalists have designed numerous tests of the quality of understanding false beliefs and tend to refer to this capacity as ‘a theory of mind’. We prefer the term mentalisation or reflective function which denotes the understanding of one’s own as well as others’ behaviour in mental state terms.
Say a three-year-old sees his friend, Maxi, hiding a piece of chocolate in a box, saying that he has to leave now but will come back to eat it later (Perner, 1991). After Maxi leaves, the child sees the experimenter move the chocolate to a basket. The child is asked: "Where will Maxi look for the chocolate, when he comes back?" The three year olds tend to predict that Maxi will look in the basket where the chocolate actually is, rather than in the box where he left it. Four and five year olds are already able to predict Maxi’s behaviour on the basis of what one might expect to be his belief, that the chocolate will still be where he left it. The four year old is said to have "a theory of mind", which is indicated by his ability to attribute false beliefs (Wimmer & Perner, 1983). He adopts an intentional stance and reasons in terms of the beliefs that may be attributed to Maxi. The three year old, however, is basing his prediction on his own representation of reality, and not on the other’s mind state.
One way to interpret this finding is that the three-year-old’s expectations are based on a nonmentalistic, "teleological" model of behaviour, rather than a mentalisitic intentional one (Gergely & Csibra, 1997). Within this simpler, teleological, model, the behavior of human objects is interpreted in terms of visible outcomes rather than inferred desires, and constraints of physical reality rather than attributed beliefs about reality. The three-year-old child in the Maxi task bases his/her prediction on an assumption of rational action presupposing that the other will do whatever is most rational to bring about the future goal state (to eat the chocolate), given the current state of external reality (that the chocolate is in the basket).
In fact, the capacity to discriminate between rational and non-rational actions has been demonstrated as early as 9 months of age (Gergely, Nadasdy, Csibra, & Biro, 1995). Infants were shown a computer-animated display depicting a small circle repeatedly jumping over a wall and making contact with a large circle on the other side. With repeated presentations, infants become "habituated", losing interest in the display. At this point, the infant is presented with one of two new displays. In both cases the wall is removed: in one case the small circle now approaches the large one directly (in a straight line), in the other it performs exactly the same jumping approach as before. Infants show surprise at the latter of the displays but not the former, indicating that they expected the circle to act ‘rationally’, i.e. to approach the target object by the shortest available route. We argue that the young child’s teleological interpretation of action is transformed into a mentalizing one during the second and third years. By 18 months (but not yet at 14) infants show a mentalistic understanding of desire (Meltzoff, 1995; Repacholi & Gopnik, 1997) being already able to understand that another person’s actions may be driven by desires other than the child’s own. At this stage the young child also becomes able to infer the other’s intention when the person uses new words to label objects unfamiliar to the child (Baldwin & Moses, 1996; Tomasello, Strosberg, & Akhtar, 1996). During the second year children already talk about desire states of self and other, and in the third year talk about beliefs also emerges (Bartsch & Wellman, 1995). A full-fledged mentalizing ability as indicated by the capacity to attribute false beliefs in theory of mind tasks is achieved towards the end of the third year (Perner, 1991).
The acquisition of "a theory of mind" is far from the end-point of this developmental process. In fact, it might be argued that reflective function is never fully achieved. At moments of high arousal, in the context of intimate relationships, we all find it hard to construct accurate representations of the mental word of the other. We reason about the behaviour of those close to us on the basis of what seems obvious, what is visible, the physical rather than the mental world. If we use mental states, these tend to be stereotypic, distorted, or confused overly analytical and inaccurate. We have attempted to operationalise individual differences in adults’ mentalising capacities. Our operationalisation was relatively simple, based on the presence of unequivocal descriptions of mental states (e.g. false beliefs) in the narrative. To score high on these ratings attachment narratives had to show awareness of mental states, manifest explicit efforts to tease out the internal reasons behind behaviour, show awareness that a child’s thoughts and feelings are likely to differ from those of an adult, and reflect a sensitivity to the mental states of the interviewer (Fonagy, Target, Steele, & Steele, 1998). The measure correlates only negligibly with I.Q. and educational background. We were curious to know if the extent of reflective observations about the mental states of self and others in AAI narratives could predict infant security. Reflectiveness ratings made before the child’s birth powerfully predicted the child’s attachment security in the 2nd year of life. Both fathers and mothers who were rated high in this capacity were three or four times more likely to have secure children than parents whose reflective capacity was poor (Fonagy, Steele, Moran, Steele, & Higgitt, 1991a).
The capacity for understanding the mental states that lie behind the parent’s behaviour may be particularly important when the child is exposed to unfavourable experiences, in the extreme, abuse or trauma. We divided our sample into those who had reported significant deprivation (overcrowding, parental mental illness) and those who had not. Our prediction was that mothers in the deprived group (childhood separations, would be far more likely to have children securely attached to them if their reflective function rating was high. All of the mothers in the deprived group with high reflectiveness ratings had children who were secure with them, whereas only 1 out of 17 of deprived mothers with low ratings did so. Our findings imply that this cycle of disadvantage may be interrupted if the caregiver has acquired a capacity to reflect productively on mental experience (Fonagy, Steele, Steele, Higgitt, & Target, 1994).
Mentalising and the development of the self
Not only are parents high in reflective capacity more likely to promote secure attachment in the child, particularly if their own childhood experiences were adverse, but also secure attachment may be a key facilitator of reflective capacity (Fonagy et al., 1995a). In our longitudinal study of 92 children, the proportion of secure children was twice as high in the group which passed a false belief task, compared to the group which failed. Mother’s reflective function was also associated with the child’s success. 80% of children whose mothers were above the median in reflective function passed, whereas only 56% of those whose mothers were below did so. The caregiver’s reflective function predicted attachment security which, in its turn, predicted the precocious acquisition of a theory of mind. Attachment to father also appeared to contribute to this developmental achievement. On a test of second-order mentalising skills, where the child is required to predict the behaviour of a person on the basis of that person’s beliefs about a third person’s false beliefs, those secure with both parents were most likely to succeed whereas those secure with neither parent were least likely to do so.
These results suggest that the parents’ capacity to observe the child’s mind facilitates the child’s general understanding of minds through the mediation of secure attachment. A reflective caregiver increases the likelihood of the child’s secure attachment which, in turn, facilitates the development of mentalisation. We assume that a secure attachment relationship provides a congenial context for the child to explore the mind of the caregiver, and in this way to learn about minds. The philosopher Hegel (1807) suggested that it is only through exploring the mind of the other that the child develops full appreciation of the nature of mental states. Reflectiveness in the child is facilitated by secure attachment. The process is intersubjective: the child gets to know the caregiver’s mind as the caregiver endeavours to understand and contain the mental state of the child.
In elucidating this process I would like to suggest three critical components. These are: (1) the role of mirroring, (2) the move to the interpretation of the caregiver’s behaviour in intentional rather than teleological terms, and (3) the integration of a primitive dual form of psychic reality into a singular mentalising representation of the mind.
1. The Role of Mirroring
Second-order (or symbolic) representations of mental states in our view evolve in the context of attachment relationships. The child’s concept of emotions is arrived at by introspection (Gergely & Watson, 1996; Target & Fonagy, 1996). Anxiety for the infant, for example, is associated with a confusing mixture of physiological experiences, behaviours and visual images. Once these become symbolically bound, the corresponding experience at a mentalised or symbolic secondary level will be one of fear or of anxiety. This symbolic binding process is essential for the child to be able to label the experience as one of a specific emotion. This knowledge is not inherent. Assume that the child’s constitutional or physical self is in a state of arousal. Associated with this are signals (non-verbal expressions, facial as well as vocal). The caregiver resonates with these and ideally reflects on her internal experience and generates an appropriate responsive expression. Such mirroring displays are innate and generated non-consciously by the caregiver (Meltzoff, 1993). The mother’s representation of the infant’s affect is represented by the child and "mapped on to" the infant’s constitutional self-state (Rogers & Pennington, 1991). The discrepancy between the child’s original experience and the internalisation of the caregiver’s mirroring representation is helpful insofar as it allows this somewhat modified representation (which is the same yet not the same) to become a higher order representation of the infant’s experience.
Within this model mirroring would be expected to fail if it is either too close to the infant’s experience or too remote from it. If the mirroring is too accurate, the perception itself can become a source of fear and it loses its symbolic potential. If it is unavailable, or is contaminated with the mother’s own preoccupation, the process of self-development is profoundly compromised. We may presume that individuals for whom the symptoms of anxiety signify catastrophes (e.g. heart attack, imminent death etc.) have second-order representations of their emotional responses which cannot be limited in intensity through symbolization, perhaps because the original mirroring by the primary caregiver exaggerated the infant’s emotions.
Admittedly this is a speculative model, but it is empirically testable. It might help answer the thorny question of why individuals with panic disorders attribute immense significance to physiologically relatively mild levels of disequilibrium. The suggestion here is that the secondary representation, or symbolic representation, of affect in these cases contains too much of the primary experience; hence, instead of labelling the experience having the potential to attenuate it, it tends to stimulate and exacerbate symptoms of the affect state, which in turn accentuates the secondary expression, in a cycle of escalating panic. In a recent study (Fonagy et al., 1995b), we have confirmed that mothers who soothe their distressed 8 month olds most effectively following an injection rapidly reflect the child’s emotion, but this mirroring is mixed with other affects (smiling, questioning, mocking display and the like). In displaying such "complex affect" (Fónagy & Fónagy, 1987) they ensure that the infant recognizes their emotion as analogous to, but not isomorphic with, their experience and thus the process of symbol formation may begin. In this way, the representational mapping between affect of self and emotions of others, the exchange of affect between young child and caregiver, provides a unique source of information to the child about his own internal states.
The child who looks for a way of managing his distress identifies in the response of the caregiver a representation of his mental state which he may internalize and use as part of a higher order strategy of affect regulation. The secure caregiver soothes by combining a "mirror" with a display incompatible with the child’s affect (thus perhaps implying coping). This formulation of sensitivity has much in common with the British psychoanalyst, Wilfred Bion’s (1962) notion of the role of the mother’s capacity to mentally "contain" the affect state intolerable for the baby, and respond in terms of physical care in a manner that acknowledges the child’s mental state yet serves to modulate unmanageable feelings. The finding that the clarity and coherence of the mother’s representation of the child mediates between her attachment status and her behavior is certainly consistent with this model (Slade, Belsky, Aber, & Phelps, in press).
We suggest that the meaning or sense of affect develops out of the integrated representation of the affect in self and other. The combination of the representation of self experience and the representation of the reaction of the caregiver elaborates the child’s teleological model of the mind, and ultimately enables him to interpret and understand affective displays in others as well as arriving at the regulation and control of his own emotions. The representational mapping of emotion displays and self experience is seen here as a prototypical instance of caregiver sensitivity, which, as we shall attempt to demonstrate, is likely to be an important component of the development of mentalizing. The reflective function of the caregiver prompts the child to begin organizing self-experience according to clusters of responses which will eventually come to be verbally labelled as specific emotions (or desires). The high contingent response is the means by which this mapping can take place. The child’s affective experiences are given further meaning by becoming associated with clusters of reality constraints within the parent-infant interaction (leading to rudimentary beliefs about the causes and consequences of his emotional state).
Peter , PhD, FBA
Paper to the Developmental and Psychoanalytic Discussion Group, American Psychoanalytic Association Meeting, Washington DC 13 May 1999
The system as a bio-social mechanism of homeostatic regulation
Attachment theory, developed by John Bowlby (Bowlby, 1969; Bowlby, 1973; Bowlby, 1980), postulates a universal human need to form close affectional bonds. At its core is the reciprocity of early relationships, which is a precondition of normal development probably in all mammals, including humans (Hofer, 1995). The attachment behaviours of the human infant (e.g. proximity seeking, smiling, clinging) are reciprocated by adult attachment behaviours (touching, holding, soothing) and these responses strengthen the attachment behaviour of the infant toward that particular adult. The activation of attachment behaviours depends on the infant’s evaluation of a range of environmental signals which results in the subjective experience of security or insecurity. The experience of security is the goal of the attachment system, which is thus first and foremost a regulator of emotional experience (Sroufe, 1996). In this sense it lies at the heart of many forms of mental disorder and the entire psychotherapeutic enterprise.
None of us is born with the capacity to regulate our own emotional reactions. A dyadic regulatory system evolves where the infants’ signals of moment to moment changes in their state that are understood and responded to by the caregiver thereby achieving their regulation. The infant learns that arousal in the presence of the caregiver will not lead to disorganisation beyond his coping capabilities. The caregiver will be there to re-establish equilibrium. In states of uncontrollable arousal, the infant will come to seek physical proximity to the caregiver in the hope of soothing and the recovery of homeostasis. The infant’s behaviour by the end of the first year is purposeful, and apparently based on specific expectations. His past experiences with the caregiver are aggregated into representational systems which Bowlby (1973) termed ‘internal working models’. Thus, the attachment system is an open bio-social homeostatic regulatory system.
Patterns of attachment in infancy
The second great pioneer of attachment theory, Mary Ainsworth (1969; 1985; Ainsworth, Blehar, Waters, & Wall, 1978), developed the well-known laboratory based procedure for observing infant’s internal working models in action. Infants, briefly separated from their caregiver in a situation unfamiliar to them, show one of four patterns of behaviour. Infants classified as Secure explore readily in the presence of the primary caregiver, are anxious in the presence of the stranger and avoid her, are distressed by their caregivers’ brief absence, rapidly seek contact with the caregiver afterwards, and are reassured by this. The infant returns to exploration. Some infants, who appear to be made less anxious by separation, may not seek proximity with the caregiver following separation, and may not prefer the caregiver over the stranger; these infants are designated ‘Anxious/Avoidant’. A third category, ‘Anxious/Resistant’ infants show limited exploration and play, tend to be highly distressed by the separation, but have great difficulty in settling afterwards, showing struggling, stiffness, continued crying, or fuss in a passive way. The caregiver’s presence or attempts at comforting fail to reassure, and the infant’s anxiety and anger appear to prevent them from deriving comfort from proximity.
Secure infants’ behaviour is based on the experience of well co-ordinated, sensitive interactions where the caregiver is rarely over-arousing and is able to restabilise the child’s disorganising emotional responses. Therefore, they remain relatively organised in stressful situations. Negative emotions feel less threatening, and can be experienced as meaningful and communicative (Grossman, Grossmann, & Schwan, 1986; Sroufe, 1979; Sroufe, 1996).
Anxious/Avoidantly attached children are presumed to have had experiences where their emotional arousal was not restabilised by the caregiver, or where they were over aroused through intrusive parenting; therefore they over-regulatetheir affect and avoid situations that are likely to be distressing. Anxious/Resistantly attached children under-regulate, heightening their expression of distress possibly in an effort to elicit the expectable response of the caregiver. There is a low threshold for threat, and the child becomes preoccupied with having contact with the caregiver, but frustrated even when it is available (Sroufe, 1996).
A fourth group of infants exhibits seemingly undirected behaviour, giving the impression of disorganisation and disorientation (Main & Solomon, 1990). Infants who manifest freezing, hand clapping, head-banging, the wish to escape the situation even in the presence of the caregiver, are referred to as ‘Disorganised/Disoriented’. It is generally held that for such infants the caregiver has served as a source of both fear and reassurance, thus arousal of the attachment behavioural system produces strong conflicting motivations. Not surprisingly, a history of severe neglect or physical or sexual abuse is often associated with this pattern (Cicchetti & Beeghly, 1987; Main & Hesse, 1990). I would like to consider this group in much greater detail, this afternoon.
The continuity of patterns of attachment
Bowlby proposed that internal working models of the self and others provide prototypes for all later relationships. Such models are relatively stable across the lifespan (Collins & Read, 1994). Early experiences of flexible access to feelings are regarded as formative by attachment theorists. The autonomous sense of self emerges fully from secure parent-infant relationships (Emde & Buchsbaum, 1990; Fonagy et al., 1995a; Lieberman & Pawl, 1990). Most importantly the increased control of the secure child permits him to move toward the ownership of inner experience, and toward understanding self and others as intentional beings whose behaviour is organised by mental states, thoughts, feelings, beliefs and desires (Fonagy et al., 1995a; Sroufe, 1990). Consistent with this, prospective longitudinal research has demonstrated that children with a history of secure attachment are independently rated as more resilient, self-reliant, socially oriented (Sroufe, 1983; Waters, Wippman, & Sroufe, 1979), empathic to distress (Kestenbaum, Farber, & Sroufe, 1989), with deeper relationships (Sroufe, 1983; Sroufe, Egeland, & Kreutzer, 1990).
Prediction from adult attachment measures
The stability of attachment is demonstrated by longitudinal studies of infants assessed with the Strange Situation and followed up in adolescence or young adulthood with the Adult Attachment Interview (AAI) (George, Kaplan, & Main, 1996). I assume most of you are familiar with this wonderful structured clinical instrument which elicits narrative histories of childhood attachment relationships – the characteristics of early relationships, experiences of separation, illness, punishment, loss, maltreatment or abuse. The AAI scoring system (Main & Goldwyn, 1994) classifies individuals intoSecure/Autonomous, Insecure/Dismissing, Insecure/Preoccupied or Unresolved with respect to loss or trauma, categories based on the structural qualities of narratives of early experiences. While autonomous individuals value attachment relationships, coherently integrate memories into a meaningful narrative and regard these as formative, insecure individuals are poor at integrating memories of experience with the meaning of that experience. Those dismissing of attachment show avoidance in denying memories, idealizing or devaluing (or both idealizing and devaluing) early relationships. Preoccupied individuals tend to be confused, angry or passive in relation to attachment figures, often still complaining of childhood slights, echoing the protests of the resistant infant. Unresolved individuals give indications of significant disorganisation in their attachment relationship representation in semantic or syntactic confusions in their narratives concerning childhood trauma or a recent loss. Again, we shall revisit this clinically most important group this afternoon.
Three major longitudinal studies (Hamilton, 1994; Main, 1997; Waters, Merrick, Albersheim, Treboux, & Crowell, 1995) have shown a 68-75% correspondence between attachment classifications in infancy and classifications in adulthood. This is an unparalleled level of consistency between behaviour observed in infancy and outcomes in adulthood. Obviously, such individual differences may well be maintained by consistent environments as well as by patterns laid down in the first year of life.
Attachment relationships play a key role in the transgenerational transmission of deprivation. Secure adults are 3 or 4 times more likely to have children who are securely attached to them (van IJzendoorn, 1995). This is true even where parental attachment is assessed before the birth of the child (Benoit & Parker, 1994; Fonagy, Steele, & Steele, 1991b; Radojevic, 1992; Steele, Steele, & Fonagy, 1996; Ward & Carlson, 1995). Parental attachment patterns predict variance in addition to temperament measures or contextual factors, such as life events, social support and psychopathology (Steele, Steele, & Fonagy, in preparation). How is such transgenerational transmission mediated? Genetics may appear to provide an obvious explanation. The early findings of an ongoing twin study in our laboratory have yielded no evidence of differential levels of concordance of attachment classification between identical and non-identical twins (Fearon, 1998). Attachment theorists have assumed that securely attached adults are more sensitive to their children’s needs thus fostering an expectation in the infant that dysregulation will be rapidly and effectively met (Belsky, Rosenberger, & Crnic, 1995; De Wolff & van IJzendoorn, 1997). Disappointingly, standard measures of caregiver sensitivity do not appear to explain at all well transgenerational consistencies in attachment classification (van IJzendoorn, 1995).
Attachment and mentalising: The move from a teleological to a mentalistic construal of attachment relationships in development
To do so, we have to explore a further aspect of the determinants of attachment. Mary Main and Inge Bretherton independently drew attention to what the philosopher Dennett called the "intentional stance". Dennett (1987) stressed that human beings try to understand each other in terms of mental states: thoughts and feelings, beliefs and desires, in order to make sense of and, even more important, to anticipate each others’ actions. If the child is able to attribute an unresponsive mother’s apparently rejecting behaviour to her sadness about a loss, rather than simply feeling helpless in the face of it, the child is protected from confusion and a negative view of himself. The hallmark of the intentional stance is the child’s recognition at around 3-4 years that behaviour may be based on a mistaken belief. Developmentalists have designed numerous tests of the quality of understanding false beliefs and tend to refer to this capacity as ‘a theory of mind’. We prefer the term mentalisation or reflective function which denotes the understanding of one’s own as well as others’ behaviour in mental state terms.
Say a three-year-old sees his friend, Maxi, hiding a piece of chocolate in a box, saying that he has to leave now but will come back to eat it later (Perner, 1991). After Maxi leaves, the child sees the experimenter move the chocolate to a basket. The child is asked: "Where will Maxi look for the chocolate, when he comes back?" The three year olds tend to predict that Maxi will look in the basket where the chocolate actually is, rather than in the box where he left it. Four and five year olds are already able to predict Maxi’s behaviour on the basis of what one might expect to be his belief, that the chocolate will still be where he left it. The four year old is said to have "a theory of mind", which is indicated by his ability to attribute false beliefs (Wimmer & Perner, 1983). He adopts an intentional stance and reasons in terms of the beliefs that may be attributed to Maxi. The three year old, however, is basing his prediction on his own representation of reality, and not on the other’s mind state.
One way to interpret this finding is that the three-year-old’s expectations are based on a nonmentalistic, "teleological" model of behaviour, rather than a mentalisitic intentional one (Gergely & Csibra, 1997). Within this simpler, teleological, model, the behavior of human objects is interpreted in terms of visible outcomes rather than inferred desires, and constraints of physical reality rather than attributed beliefs about reality. The three-year-old child in the Maxi task bases his/her prediction on an assumption of rational action presupposing that the other will do whatever is most rational to bring about the future goal state (to eat the chocolate), given the current state of external reality (that the chocolate is in the basket).
In fact, the capacity to discriminate between rational and non-rational actions has been demonstrated as early as 9 months of age (Gergely, Nadasdy, Csibra, & Biro, 1995). Infants were shown a computer-animated display depicting a small circle repeatedly jumping over a wall and making contact with a large circle on the other side. With repeated presentations, infants become "habituated", losing interest in the display. At this point, the infant is presented with one of two new displays. In both cases the wall is removed: in one case the small circle now approaches the large one directly (in a straight line), in the other it performs exactly the same jumping approach as before. Infants show surprise at the latter of the displays but not the former, indicating that they expected the circle to act ‘rationally’, i.e. to approach the target object by the shortest available route. We argue that the young child’s teleological interpretation of action is transformed into a mentalizing one during the second and third years. By 18 months (but not yet at 14) infants show a mentalistic understanding of desire (Meltzoff, 1995; Repacholi & Gopnik, 1997) being already able to understand that another person’s actions may be driven by desires other than the child’s own. At this stage the young child also becomes able to infer the other’s intention when the person uses new words to label objects unfamiliar to the child (Baldwin & Moses, 1996; Tomasello, Strosberg, & Akhtar, 1996). During the second year children already talk about desire states of self and other, and in the third year talk about beliefs also emerges (Bartsch & Wellman, 1995). A full-fledged mentalizing ability as indicated by the capacity to attribute false beliefs in theory of mind tasks is achieved towards the end of the third year (Perner, 1991).
The acquisition of "a theory of mind" is far from the end-point of this developmental process. In fact, it might be argued that reflective function is never fully achieved. At moments of high arousal, in the context of intimate relationships, we all find it hard to construct accurate representations of the mental word of the other. We reason about the behaviour of those close to us on the basis of what seems obvious, what is visible, the physical rather than the mental world. If we use mental states, these tend to be stereotypic, distorted, or confused overly analytical and inaccurate. We have attempted to operationalise individual differences in adults’ mentalising capacities. Our operationalisation was relatively simple, based on the presence of unequivocal descriptions of mental states (e.g. false beliefs) in the narrative. To score high on these ratings attachment narratives had to show awareness of mental states, manifest explicit efforts to tease out the internal reasons behind behaviour, show awareness that a child’s thoughts and feelings are likely to differ from those of an adult, and reflect a sensitivity to the mental states of the interviewer (Fonagy, Target, Steele, & Steele, 1998). The measure correlates only negligibly with I.Q. and educational background. We were curious to know if the extent of reflective observations about the mental states of self and others in AAI narratives could predict infant security. Reflectiveness ratings made before the child’s birth powerfully predicted the child’s attachment security in the 2nd year of life. Both fathers and mothers who were rated high in this capacity were three or four times more likely to have secure children than parents whose reflective capacity was poor (Fonagy, Steele, Moran, Steele, & Higgitt, 1991a).
The capacity for understanding the mental states that lie behind the parent’s behaviour may be particularly important when the child is exposed to unfavourable experiences, in the extreme, abuse or trauma. We divided our sample into those who had reported significant deprivation (overcrowding, parental mental illness) and those who had not. Our prediction was that mothers in the deprived group (childhood separations, would be far more likely to have children securely attached to them if their reflective function rating was high. All of the mothers in the deprived group with high reflectiveness ratings had children who were secure with them, whereas only 1 out of 17 of deprived mothers with low ratings did so. Our findings imply that this cycle of disadvantage may be interrupted if the caregiver has acquired a capacity to reflect productively on mental experience (Fonagy, Steele, Steele, Higgitt, & Target, 1994).
Mentalising and the development of the self
Not only are parents high in reflective capacity more likely to promote secure attachment in the child, particularly if their own childhood experiences were adverse, but also secure attachment may be a key facilitator of reflective capacity (Fonagy et al., 1995a). In our longitudinal study of 92 children, the proportion of secure children was twice as high in the group which passed a false belief task, compared to the group which failed. Mother’s reflective function was also associated with the child’s success. 80% of children whose mothers were above the median in reflective function passed, whereas only 56% of those whose mothers were below did so. The caregiver’s reflective function predicted attachment security which, in its turn, predicted the precocious acquisition of a theory of mind. Attachment to father also appeared to contribute to this developmental achievement. On a test of second-order mentalising skills, where the child is required to predict the behaviour of a person on the basis of that person’s beliefs about a third person’s false beliefs, those secure with both parents were most likely to succeed whereas those secure with neither parent were least likely to do so.
These results suggest that the parents’ capacity to observe the child’s mind facilitates the child’s general understanding of minds through the mediation of secure attachment. A reflective caregiver increases the likelihood of the child’s secure attachment which, in turn, facilitates the development of mentalisation. We assume that a secure attachment relationship provides a congenial context for the child to explore the mind of the caregiver, and in this way to learn about minds. The philosopher Hegel (1807) suggested that it is only through exploring the mind of the other that the child develops full appreciation of the nature of mental states. Reflectiveness in the child is facilitated by secure attachment. The process is intersubjective: the child gets to know the caregiver’s mind as the caregiver endeavours to understand and contain the mental state of the child.
In elucidating this process I would like to suggest three critical components. These are: (1) the role of mirroring, (2) the move to the interpretation of the caregiver’s behaviour in intentional rather than teleological terms, and (3) the integration of a primitive dual form of psychic reality into a singular mentalising representation of the mind.
1. The Role of Mirroring
Second-order (or symbolic) representations of mental states in our view evolve in the context of attachment relationships. The child’s concept of emotions is arrived at by introspection (Gergely & Watson, 1996; Target & Fonagy, 1996). Anxiety for the infant, for example, is associated with a confusing mixture of physiological experiences, behaviours and visual images. Once these become symbolically bound, the corresponding experience at a mentalised or symbolic secondary level will be one of fear or of anxiety. This symbolic binding process is essential for the child to be able to label the experience as one of a specific emotion. This knowledge is not inherent. Assume that the child’s constitutional or physical self is in a state of arousal. Associated with this are signals (non-verbal expressions, facial as well as vocal). The caregiver resonates with these and ideally reflects on her internal experience and generates an appropriate responsive expression. Such mirroring displays are innate and generated non-consciously by the caregiver (Meltzoff, 1993). The mother’s representation of the infant’s affect is represented by the child and "mapped on to" the infant’s constitutional self-state (Rogers & Pennington, 1991). The discrepancy between the child’s original experience and the internalisation of the caregiver’s mirroring representation is helpful insofar as it allows this somewhat modified representation (which is the same yet not the same) to become a higher order representation of the infant’s experience.
Within this model mirroring would be expected to fail if it is either too close to the infant’s experience or too remote from it. If the mirroring is too accurate, the perception itself can become a source of fear and it loses its symbolic potential. If it is unavailable, or is contaminated with the mother’s own preoccupation, the process of self-development is profoundly compromised. We may presume that individuals for whom the symptoms of anxiety signify catastrophes (e.g. heart attack, imminent death etc.) have second-order representations of their emotional responses which cannot be limited in intensity through symbolization, perhaps because the original mirroring by the primary caregiver exaggerated the infant’s emotions.
Admittedly this is a speculative model, but it is empirically testable. It might help answer the thorny question of why individuals with panic disorders attribute immense significance to physiologically relatively mild levels of disequilibrium. The suggestion here is that the secondary representation, or symbolic representation, of affect in these cases contains too much of the primary experience; hence, instead of labelling the experience having the potential to attenuate it, it tends to stimulate and exacerbate symptoms of the affect state, which in turn accentuates the secondary expression, in a cycle of escalating panic. In a recent study (Fonagy et al., 1995b), we have confirmed that mothers who soothe their distressed 8 month olds most effectively following an injection rapidly reflect the child’s emotion, but this mirroring is mixed with other affects (smiling, questioning, mocking display and the like). In displaying such "complex affect" (Fónagy & Fónagy, 1987) they ensure that the infant recognizes their emotion as analogous to, but not isomorphic with, their experience and thus the process of symbol formation may begin. In this way, the representational mapping between affect of self and emotions of others, the exchange of affect between young child and caregiver, provides a unique source of information to the child about his own internal states.
The child who looks for a way of managing his distress identifies in the response of the caregiver a representation of his mental state which he may internalize and use as part of a higher order strategy of affect regulation. The secure caregiver soothes by combining a "mirror" with a display incompatible with the child’s affect (thus perhaps implying coping). This formulation of sensitivity has much in common with the British psychoanalyst, Wilfred Bion’s (1962) notion of the role of the mother’s capacity to mentally "contain" the affect state intolerable for the baby, and respond in terms of physical care in a manner that acknowledges the child’s mental state yet serves to modulate unmanageable feelings. The finding that the clarity and coherence of the mother’s representation of the child mediates between her attachment status and her behavior is certainly consistent with this model (Slade, Belsky, Aber, & Phelps, in press).
We suggest that the meaning or sense of affect develops out of the integrated representation of the affect in self and other. The combination of the representation of self experience and the representation of the reaction of the caregiver elaborates the child’s teleological model of the mind, and ultimately enables him to interpret and understand affective displays in others as well as arriving at the regulation and control of his own emotions. The representational mapping of emotion displays and self experience is seen here as a prototypical instance of caregiver sensitivity, which, as we shall attempt to demonstrate, is likely to be an important component of the development of mentalizing. The reflective function of the caregiver prompts the child to begin organizing self-experience according to clusters of responses which will eventually come to be verbally labelled as specific emotions (or desires). The high contingent response is the means by which this mapping can take place. The child’s affective experiences are given further meaning by becoming associated with clusters of reality constraints within the parent-infant interaction (leading to rudimentary beliefs about the causes and consequences of his emotional state).